top of page
17979499313212149_edited.jpg
2BD61A16-11CE-48EA-9393-3B5D0548EB1B_1_105_c.jpeg
IMG_9219-Modifica.jpg

BOOKS

Temporal Cognition in Animals. (Elements Series in Philosophy of Biology) Cambridge University Press. Under Contract. [request preprint]

​

Humans and non-human animals alike rely on temporal cues to guide behaviours. This book aims to explore the presence of genuine temporal cognition in non-human animals, specifically focusing on whether animals possess temporal representations rather than mere temporal sensitivities. Additionally, this book addresses the evolution of cognitive architectures that enable temporal cognition and discusses the philosophical implications of time representation. Findings in animal cognition challenge the long-standing view that non-human animals lack the ability to mentally represent time. By presenting case studies from the wild—starting from the coordinated hunting strategies and anticipatory foraging behaviours of apes—this book provides compelling evidence for temporal cognition through the mental representation of time. Expanding on these paradigmatic findings, the book offers a comparative analysis across various species, including birds, marine mammals, and human infants, to examine how different species represent and coordinate their actions with time. By bridging empirical research with philosophical inquiry, the book fills a critical gap in the literature and redefines our understanding of temporal cognition in non-human animals. 

JOURNAL ARTICLES AND BOOK CHAPTERS

Commitment: in and out of control. SI on 'Control and Commitment Philosophical, Psychological, and Neuroscientific Perspectives'. [with Martina Fanghella]. New Ideas in Psychology. Forthcoming. [request preprint]

​

Commitment is often viewed as an essential component of human agency, involving a blend of cognitive, affective, and volitional processes that enable individuals to adhere to chosen goals and values. However, the dynamics of commitment can shift dramatically, oscillating between states where it is actively cultivated and maintained, and situations where it feels beyond one's direct control. By integrating insights from philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience, this paper examines how various forms of commitment intersect with the mechanisms of control, such as self-regulation, motivational structures, and neural substrates associated with decision-making.

Perception in the mirror: the influence of self-beliefs. [with Antonella Tramacere]. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. R&R [request preprint]

​

Mirrors are more than reflective surfaces; they are portals to self-perception influenced by a tapestry of developmental, psychological, and cultural factors. In this paper, we explore the interplay between these factors by investigating the effect of self-beliefs on mirror self-perception and clarifying how negative views about oneself’s outward appearance develop. We analyse the literature on mirror self-recognition and the development of self-beliefs, revealing a reciprocal relationship between mirror gazing and what one believes about oneself. Our discussion highlights the impact of emotionally charged self-beliefs in accentuating perceived physical flaws, influencing mirror self-perception. Our proposal offers insights into body dysmorphic disorders, underscoring the significance of the belief-perception interplay in this and related pathologies.

Evolutionary Primitive Social EntitiesPhilosophia. R&R [request preprint]

​

Social entities only exist in virtue of collective acceptance or recognition, or acknowledgement by two or more individuals in the context of joint activities. Joint activities are made possible by the coordination of plans for action, and the coordination of plans for action is made possible by the capacity for collective intentionality. This paper investigates how primitive is the capacity that nonhuman animals have to create social entities, by individuating how primitive is the capacity for collective intentionality. I present a novel argument for the evolutionary primitiveness of social entities, by showing that the collective intentions upon which these social entities are created and shared are metaphysically reducible to the relevant individual intentions.

Temporal Cognition in Apes. [with Gerardo Viera]. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. Forthcoming. [request preprint]

​

In humans, at least some of our ability to coordinate our actions with the timing of events in our world is due to our capacities for temporal cognition. However, controversy arises when we turn our attention to the animal world. In this paper, we will argue that apes, especially Taï Chimpanzees, are capable of genuine temporal cognition. That is, they are able to mentally represent and reason about time in cognition. We do this by developing a novel analysis of the mental representation of time.

All Animals are Conscious in Their Own Way: Comparing the Markers Hypothesis with the Universal Consciousness HypothesisFrontiers in Psychology. 2024. [Published]

​

This paper evaluates recent advancements in the debate on animal consciousness, comparing the marker hypothesis with the universal consciousness hypothesis. It discusses the use of consciousness tests (C-tests) for identifying conscious beings, a method supported by Bayne et al.’ s (2024) and compares this with Andrews's (2024) call for assuming all animals are conscious. The paper argues for a balanced approach to studying consciousness that acknowledges species-specific consciousness without relying solely on C-tests. It suggests Dung and Newen's (2023) framework as a synthesis of these views, offering a method that combines scientific rigour with ethical considerations.

Two Models of Mind Blanking [with Sara Parmigiani, Toshikazu Kawagoe et al.]. European Journal of Neuroscience. 2023. [Published]

​

Mind blanking is a mental state in which attention does not bring any perceptual input into conscious awareness. As this state is still largely unexplored, we suggest that a comprehensive understanding of mind blanking can be achieved through a multifaceted approach combining self-assessment methods, neuroimaging, and neuromodulation. In this article, we explain how EEG and TMS could be combined to help determine whether mind blanking is associated with a lack of mental content or a lack of linguistically or conceptually determinable mental content. We also question whether mind blanking occurs spontaneously or intentionally and whether these two forms are instantiated by the same or different neural correlates.

Introducing individual sentience profiles in nonhuman primate neuroscience researchCurrent Research in Neurobiology. 2023. [Published]

​

The Animal Research Declaration is committed to establishing cohesive and rigorous ethical standards to safeguard the welfare of nonhuman primates, NHPs, engaged in neuroscience research (Petkov et al., 2022 this issue). As part of this mission, there is an expanding dialogue amongst neuroscientists, philosophers and policymakers, that is centred on diverse aspects of animal welfare and scientific practice. This paper emphasises the necessity of integrating the assessment of animal sentience into the declaration. Animal sentience, in this context, refers to the recognised capacity that animals have for various kinds of subjective experience, with an associated positive or negative valence (Browning and Birch, 2022). Accordingly, NHP neuroscience researchers should work toward instituting a standardised approach for evaluating what can be termed "individual sentience profiles," representing the unique manner in which an individual NHP experiences specific events or environments. The adoption of this novel parameter would serve a triad of indispensable purposes: enhancing NHP welfare throughout research involvement, elevating the quality of life for NHPs in captivity, and refining the calibre of research outcomes. 

Animal Thought Exceeds Language of Thought [with Albert Newen]. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2023. [Published]

​

Quilty-Dunn, Porot, & Mandelbaum claim that all complex infant and animal reasoning implicate LOTH-like structures. We agree with the authors that the mental life of animals can be explained in representationalist terms, but we disagree with their idea that the complexity of mental representations is best explained by appealing to abstract concepts, and instead, we explain that it doesn’t need to.

Phenomenological qualitative methods applied to the analysis of cross-cultural experience in novel educational social contexts [with Ahmed A. Alhazmi]. Frontiers in Psychology. 2022. [Published]

​

The qualitative method of phenomenology provides a theoretical tool for educational research as it allows researchers to engage in flexible activities that can describe and help to understand complex phenomena, such as various aspects of human social experience. This article explains how to apply the framework of phenomenological qualitative analysis to educational research. The discussion within this article is relevant to those researchers interested in doing cross-cultural qualitative research and in adapting phenomenological investigations to understand students' cross-cultural lived experiences in different social educational contexts.

Experience-specific dimensions of consciousness (observable in flexible and spontaneous action planning among animals)

Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience. 2021. [Published]

​

The multidimensional framework to the study of consciousness, which comes as an alternative to a single sliding scale model, offers a set of experimental paradigms for investigating dimensions of animal consciousness, beautifully acknowledging the urge for a novel approach. One of these dimensions investigates whether nonhuman animals can flexibly and spontaneously plan for a future event, and for future desires, without relying on reinforcement learning. This is a critical question since different intentional structures for action in non-human animals are described as served by different neural mechanisms underpinning the capacity to represent temporal properties. And a lack of appreciation of this variety of intentional structures and neural correlates has led many experts to doubt that animals have access to temporal reasoning and to not recognize temporality as a mark of consciousness, and as a psychological resource for their life. With respect to this, there is a significant body of ethological evidence for planning abilities in nonhuman animals, too often overlooked, and that instead should be taken into serious account. This could contribute to assigning consciousness profiles, across and within species, that should be tailored according to an implemented and expansive use of the multidimensional framework. This cannot be fully operational in the absence of an additional tag to its dimensions of variations: the experience-specificity of consciousness.

Is that all there is? Or is chimpanzees group hunt “fair” enough?  Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2020. [Published]

​

Tomasello claims that we lack convincing evidence that nonhuman animals manifest a sense of moral obligation (i.e., the concept of fairness) in their group activities. The philosophical analysis of distinctive evidence from ethology, namely group hunting practices among chimpanzees, can help the author appreciate the distinctive character of this behaviour as a display of fairness put in practice.

Temporal representation and reasoning in non-human animals. [with Arnon Cahen]. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2019. [Published]

 

Hoerl and McCormack argue that comparative and developmental psychology teaches us that neither animals nor infants can think and reason about time. We argue that the authors neglect to take into account pivotal evidence from ethology that suggests that non-human animals do possess a capacity to represent and reason about time, namely, work done on Sumatran orangutans’ long travel calls.

Joint distal intentions: Who shares what? Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of the Social Mind. 2017. [Published]

​

The ability to think for cooperating is called Shared Intentionality (Tomasello, 2014, p. 125). The advocates of the Shared Intentionality Hypothesis maintain that this is a distinctively human skill, for humans possess a foundational ability to ascribe distal intentions to conspecifics, and to share distal intentions courtesy of this capacity. Accordingly, humans appear to be provided with a specific capacity to coordinate joint actions and plans over time. I investigate to what extent such capacity can be observed to emerge in non-human animals as well.

Collective Intentionality: a human - not a monkey - business. Phenomenology and Mind. 2016. [Published]

​

In Making the Social World, Searle makes the same claim he made in 1995: that “Human beings along with a lot of other social animals, have the capacity for collective intentionality” (Searle, 2010, p. 43). In this paper, I aim to show that Searle's overattribution' of collective intentionality to non-human animals is unjustified. Firstly, I briefly reconstruct and augment Tomasello & Rakoczy's (2007) criticism that Searle overemphasises the primitiveness of the notion of collective intentionality. Secondly, I will outline a cross-species analysis for the emergence of cooperative behaviour. Such an approach suggests that we resist Searle'soverattribution. Thirdly, I argue that Searle's six conditions of adequacy for any account of collective intentionality are incompatible with his attribution of collective intentionality to non-human animals. Finally, I conclude by noting that Searle's overattribution has important consequences for his system, as it implicates that human uniqueness begins with institutional reality rather than with collective intentionality and social ontology.

Animal mental action: planning among chimpanzeesReview of Philosophy and Psychology. 2015. [Published]

​

I offer an argument for what mental action may be like in nonhuman animals. Action planning is a type of mental action that involves a type of intention. Some intentions are the causal mental antecedents of proximal mental actions, and some intentions are the causal mental antecedents of distal mental actions. The distinction between these two types of “plan-states” is often spelled out in terms of mental content. The prominent view is that while proximal mental actions are caused by mental states with nonconceptual content, distal mental actions are caused by mental states with conceptual content. I argue that, when we are investigating animal cognition, we need a nonconceptual account for the content of intentions involved in mental actions such as action planning: non-immediate intentions. This in order to defend the claim that creatures that lack conceptual capacities are capable of entertaining plan-states, and thus of exercising mental agency in the form of action planning.

Pointing and Representing – Three Options. [with Nick Young and Bence Nanay]. HUMANA.MENTE Journal of Philosophical Studies. 2013. [Published]

​

The aim of this paper is to explore the minimal representational requirements for pointing. One-year-old children are capable of pointing: what does this tell us about their representational capacities? We analysed three options: (a) Pointing presupposes non-perceptual representations. (b) Pointing does not presuppose any representation at all. (c) Pointing presupposes perceptual representations. Rather than fully endorsing any of these three options. The aim of the paper is to explore the advantages and disadvantages of each.

EDITED JOURNAL SPECIAL ISSUES

Special Issue on 'Control and Commitment Philosophical, Psychological, and Neuroscientific Perspectives'. [co-ed. Martina Fanghella]. New Ideas in Psychology. [submissions open]

​

Commitment is not only central to personal goal achievement but also foundational for maintaining social bonds and fostering cooperation within groups. Recent research has highlighted the social factors that elicit or enhance the sense of commitment. However, there is still much to uncover about the cognitive and motivational mechanisms, including control mechanisms, that underpin this sense of commitment. How do these mechanisms interact to help individuals resist distractions and stay on course toward their objectives?

 

Invited Contributions:
Felipe de Brigard (Duke University), Sam Murray (Providence University) & Kristina Krasich (Duke University)
Juan Pablo Bermúdez (University of Southampton & Externado de Colombia University)
Polaris Koi (Turku University)
John Michael & Marcell Székely (University of Milan)
Joshua Shepherd (Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona)

​

PHD THESIS

Animal Intention. Universiteit Antwerpen. 2015. [Published]

​

There are actions that we could not perform without intending them. Some intentions are the causal components of action plans, and the function of action plans is that of guiding one or many agent’s behaviour towards the successful accomplishment of distal goals. The capacity to form and ascribe these mental states is also fundational to social cognition. This thesis investigates distal intentions in nonhuman animals. These are mental states that figure as the necessary causal mental antecedents of action planning and that represent plans to which individual or joint actions can be directed. Tracking the roots of the capacity for action planning and for social cognition led to ask the following questions: Do nonhuman animals have and ascribe distal intentions? Chapter 1 is introductory to the issue of animal intention; Chapter 2 defines the notion of distal intention at play in my work; Chapter 3 analyses individual distal intention; Chapter 4 analyses joint distal intentions; Chapter 5 investigates the neural correlates of individual and joint distal intentions; Chapter 6 hypothesis which role distal intentions plays in the creation of social entities.

OTHER PUBLICATIONS

The brain on (video) games. SEISMA Magazine. 2020. [Published]

"HAYVAN ZIHNI" (Animal Minds). Popular Science Magazine Türkiyë. 2018. [Published]

Frank Underwood's Intentions. The Blackwell Philosophy and Pop Culture Series2015. [Published

bottom of page